Mind engineering, habit, and human nature

Reinterprets the notion of "mind engineering" from a more neutral standpoint and offers a totally new approach to the phenomenon. The "mind" is defined as a set of beliefs, and the latter, following Charles Peirce, is interpreted as the set of habits.

Ðóáðèêà Ïñèõîëîãèÿ
Âèä ñòàòüÿ
ßçûê àíãëèéñêèé
Äàòà äîáàâëåíèÿ 14.08.2023
Ðàçìåð ôàéëà 33,8 K

Îòïðàâèòü ñâîþ õîðîøóþ ðàáîòó â áàçó çíàíèé ïðîñòî. Èñïîëüçóéòå ôîðìó, ðàñïîëîæåííóþ íèæå

Ñòóäåíòû, àñïèðàíòû, ìîëîäûå ó÷åíûå, èñïîëüçóþùèå áàçó çíàíèé â ñâîåé ó÷åáå è ðàáîòå, áóäóò âàì î÷åíü áëàãîäàðíû.

Ðàçìåùåíî íà http://www.allbest.ru/

Mind engineering, habit, and human nature

Andrii Leonov

Abstract

This paper attempts to do the following things. First, it reinterprets the notion of «mind engineering» from a more neutral standpoint and offers a totally new approach to the phenomenon. Thus, instead of looking at the phenomenon from a wholly negative perspective (such as identification of mind engineering with «brainwashing», «mind control» and other coercive and manipulatory techniques), it defines mind engineering as the process of «design/redesign, implementation/reimplementation, evaluation/reevaluation of minds». In itself, this process can be deliberate or forceful. Here, the author looks at deliberate mind engineering primarily.

Secondly, the «mind» is defined as a set of beliefs, and the latter, following Charles Peirce, is interpreted as the set of habits. The phenomenon of habit is interpreted pragmatically-hermeneutically and is defined as a «`fixed' functional interpretation of the world and one's place in it that either works or does not work». If a specific interpretation constantly works, it constitutes a «good» habit. If it does not work, it means a «bad» habit. Unlike the current social-psychological approaches to habit as goal-independent and automatic, and therefore «mindless»/non-cognitive, the author claims that habits are essentially goal-dependent, and cognitive. The habit's main goal is to resolve the problematic situation that the organism is in. Habit's cognitive element is grounded in the organism's interpretive effort that allows it to specify a problematic situation as problematic. Therefore, the connection between the organism and a situation is not direct/immediate but rather is mediated via functional interpretive meaning. In the end, mind engineering must be taken as «habit engineering», and, thus understood, the phenomenon in question can be seen as one of the key phenomena to clarify human nature.

Keywords: mind engineering, belief, habit, stream of habit, habit engineering, human nature, Peirce, James, Dewey.

Àíîòàö³ÿ

²ÍÆÅÍÅÐ²ß ÓÌÀ, ÇÂÈ×ÊÀ ÒÀ ËÞÄÑÜÊÀ ÏÐÈÐÎÄÀ

Àíäð³é Ëåîíîâ

Ó ö³é ñòàòò³ çðîáëåíà ñïðîáà äîñë³äèòè íàñòóïíå. Ïî-ïåðøå, àâòîð ïåðåîñìèñëþº ïîíÿòòÿ «³íæåíå𳿠óìà» ç 6²ËÜØ íåéòðàëüíî¿ òî÷êè çîðó òà ïðîïîíóº ÏÎÂͲÑÒÞ íîâèé ϲÄÕ²Ä äî öüîãî ôåíîìåíó. Òàêèì ÷èíîì, çàì³ñòü ïîãëÿäó íà öåé ôåíîìåí ç ñóòî íåãàòèâíî¿ òî÷êè çîðó (íàïðèêëàä, îòîòîæíåííÿ ³íæåíå𳿠óìà ç «ïðîìèâàííÿì ì³çê³â», «êîíòðîëåì ðîçóìó» òà ³íøèìè ïðèìóñîâèìè òà ìàí³ïóëÿòèâíèìè òåõí³êàìè), àâòîð âèçíà÷ຠ³íæåíåð³þ óìà ÿê ïðîöåñ «ïðîºêòóâàííÿ/ïåðåïðîºêòóâàííÿ, âïðîâàäæåí¬íÿ/ïîâòîðíîãî âïðîâàäæåííÿ, îö³íêè/ïåðåîö³íêè óìà». Ñàì ïî ñîá³ öåé ïðîöåñ ìîæå áóòè äîáðîâ³ëüíèì àáî ïðèìóñîâèì. Òóò àâòîð ðîçãëÿäຠíàñàìïåðåä äîáðîâ³ëüíó ³íæåíåð³þ óìà. Ïî-äðóãå, «óì» âèçíà÷àºòüñÿ ÿê íàá³ð ïåðåêîíàíü, à îñòàíí³, ñë³äîì çà ×àðëüçîì ϳðñîì, òðàêòóþòüñÿ ÿê íàá³ð çâè÷îê. Ôåíîìåí çâè÷êè òðàêòóºòüñÿ ïðàãìàòè÷íî-ãåðìåíåâòè÷íî ³ âèçíà÷àºòüñÿ ÿê «`ô³êñîâàíà' ôóíêö³îíàëüíà ³íòåðïðåòàö³ÿ ñâiòó òà âëàñíîãî ì³ñöÿ â íüîìó, ÿêà àáî ïðàöþº, àáî íå ïðàöþº». ßêùî êîíêðåòíà ³íòåðïðåòàö³ÿ ïîñò³éíî ïðàöþº, âîíà º «õîðîøîþ» çâè÷êîþ. ßêùî íå ïðàöþº, çíà÷èòü «ïîãàíîþ» çâè÷êîþ. Íà â³äì³íó â³ä ñó÷àñíèõ ñîö³àëüíî- ïñèõîëîã³÷íèõ ï³äõîä³â äî çâè÷êè ÿê ö³ëåíåçàëåæíî¿ òà àâòîìàòè÷íî¿, à îòæå, «áåçäóìíî¿»/íåêîãí³òèâíî¿, àâòîð ñòâåðäæóº, ùî çâè÷êè º ñóòí³- ñíî ùëåçàëåæíèìè òà êîãí¿òèâíèìè. Îñíîâíà ìåòà çâè÷êè ïîëÿãຠâ òîìó, ùîá âèð³øèòè ïðîáëåìíó ñèòóàö¿þ, â ÿê³é çíàõîäèòüñÿ îðãàí³çì. Êîãí³òèâíèé åëåìåíò çâè÷êè çàñíîâàíèé íà òòåðïðåòàöøíîìó çóñèëë¿ îðãàí³çìó, ÿêå äîçâîëÿº éîìó âèçíà÷èòè ïðîáëåìíó ñèòóàö³þ ÿê ïðîáëåì¬íó. Òîìó çâ'ÿçîê ì³æ îðãàí³çìîì ³ ñèòóàö³ºþ íå º ïðÿìèì/áåçïîñåðåäí³ì, à ñêîð³øå îïîñåðåäêîâóºòüñÿ ÷åðåç ôóíêö³îíàëüíèé ¿íòåðïðåòàö¿éíèé ñåíñ. Çðåøòîþ, ³íæåíåð³þ óìà ñë³ä ñïðèéìàòè ÿê «³íæåíåð³þ çâè÷îê», ³, ÿêùî ¿¿ ðîçóì³òè òàêèì ÷èíîì, òî ðîçãëÿíóòèé ôåíîìåí ìîæíà ðîçãëÿäàòè ÿê îäèí ç êëþ÷îâèõ ôåíîìåí³â äëÿ ïðîÿñíåííÿ ëþäñüêî¿ ïðèðîäè.

Êëþ÷îâ³ ñëîâà: ³íæåíåð³ÿ óìà, ïåðåêîíàííÿ, çâè÷êà, ïîò³ê çâè÷êè, ³íæå¬íåð³ÿ çâè÷êè, ϳðñ, Äæåéìñ, Äüþ¿.

«When we are honest with ourselves, we acknowledge that a habit has this power because it is so intimately a part of ourselves. It has a hold

upon us because we are the habit» [6, p. 21].

Introduction

mind engineering human nature

The concept of «mind engineering» usually refers to a phenomenon that seems hard to tell whether it is a fact or a fiction. There is neither a clear and precise definition, nor even an understanding of the phenomenon. Various labels are given to it such as «brainwashing», «mind control», «coercive persuasion» etc., which clearly have only negative connotations. Mind engineering, understood in the previous senses, appears more like a political tool that is used by political regimes literally to indoctrinate their political agendas unto their opponents/citizens. But I think that «mind engineering» as a concept has much more to offer than it is usually assumed.

This paper aims to reinterpret the concept of mind engineering both philosophically and psychologically, and thus, offer a totally new approach to the phenomenon. Ultimately, mind-engineering is not just about politics or manipulation, but about a better understanding of human nature. The better we understand the former, the better light it might shed on the latter.

Reinterpretation of the concept of mind engineering

The core ideas that are defended in this paper are the following.

David Chalmers [1] defines conceptual engineering as the «design, implementation, and evaluation of concepts». By analogy with the latter, I define mind engineering as the «design, implementation, and evaluation of minds».

The concept of the «mind» I interpret as the «set of beliefs», while «beliefs», following Charles Peirce, are pragmatically taken as habits. Consequently, «mind engineering» is understood as the «design, implementation, and evaluation of habits» or «habit engineering»/habit acquiring. Since habits can be creatively newly acquired or reacquired, this allows us to extend the working definition of mind engineering accordingly: it is «the process of design/redesign, implementation/reimplementation, and evaluation/reevaluation of habits».

The concept of a «habit» is approached pragmatically-hermeneutically and is understood as a «`fixed' functional interpretation of the world, and one's place in it that either works or does not work». Therefore, the final definition of the concept of «mind-engineering» would be the following: it is the process of design/redesign, implementation/reimplementation, and evaluation/ reevaluation of the «fixed» functional interpretations of the world, and one's place in it that either work or do not work.

Consequences of reinterpreting mind engineering as «habit engineering»

From (1), (2), and (3) it seems to follow that mind/habit engineering is rather a neutral term that has the following dimensions: (a) in terms of the process of the habit acquiring/«engineering» and (b) in terms of its normative significance.

In terms of the process of habit acquiring, mind engineering can be seen as deliberate or forceful.

Deliberate mind engineering signifies the process of normal education where learning new habits is experimental, and thus, is the «trial and error» process. In other words, it is «habit-engineering» that is based on the organism's/person's own initiative and is accompanied by at least some evidence and facts. It is when, following Dewey, ideas must be controlled by facts [3, p. 78-90].

Forceful mind/habit engineering is a process that is not based on an organism's/person's own initiative. Forceful mind engineering can also be divided into two subclasses: «strongly forceful» mind engineering and «weakly forceful» mind engineering. Both types refer to what is usually called «brainwashing» or what I would term «habitwashing». When «strongly forceful» mind engineering is openly realized against one's will and desire, «weakly forceful» mind engineering is rather characterized by various manipulative techniques: a victim thinks as if their new habits are acquired «deliberately» when this is not the case.

(b) In terms of its normative significance, mind engineering is positive or negative. A «positive» mind engineering signifies the acquiring of «good» habits, while a «negative» mind engineering signifies one's acquiring «bad» habits. Due to the fact that habits in themselves are norms, and as such, they are also subjects to (other) norms, mind engineering is a normative enterprise in the first place.

In this paper, I primarily focus on the deliberate aspect of mind/habit engineering, and will largely omit its forceful elements. In terms of the mind/habit engineering's normative significance, my approach will be «meta». I will not aim to specify namely what habits are «good», and what habits are «bad». But I will try to understand what makes habits normative, and how «good» habits are being distinguished from «bad» habits in principle. Overall, a philosophy and psychology of mind engineering should be understood rather as the philosophy and psychology of habit engineering, and a better understanding of this process, as well as the function and role of habits in our lives, is the proper key to a better understanding of human nature.

The structure of the paper

This paper consists of five parts. In Part 1, I critically overview some current social psychological approaches to habit. In Part 2, I look at the pragmatic understanding of beliefs as habits as it is developed by Charles Pierce. In Part 3, I show William James's perspective on habit, as it is presented in Chapter IV of his 1890 Principles. In Part 4, I extend James's approach to habit through what I call a pragmatic-hermeneutic approach to the phenomenon of habit which in itself is grounded in John Dewey's functional psychology of 1896. In Part 5, I reinterpret the concept of mind engineering as «habit engineering». Here, I argue that habits are not purely automatic/«mindless», but are essentially goal-dependent and cognitive. This part is concluded with an idea that the genuine (i.e., deliberate) process of mind-engineering is essentially akin to what Dewey called the denotative method/pattern of inquiry, or what Karl Popper termed as the hypothetic-deductive method, and as such, is possible to be fully realized in the open/democratic societies.

Part 1. Habits and social psychology. A short literature overview

The phenomenon of habit is both a philosophical and also a social psychological phenomenon. But when it comes to the latter, the study of the phenomenon in question is mostly abandoned by the discipline [26, p. 389]. My interpretation of the phenomenon of habit is grounded in the classical pragmatic tradition, and especially in the work of William James and John Dewey. The reason for that is that both philosophers made a significant influence on the development of social psychology as a discipline, and even though James's functional psychology is indeed mentioned as a forerunner of the discipline overall, and especially in the United States [10, 22], the work of John Dewey is usually omitted from the consideration, despite his groundbreaking 1896 article «The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology» [2, p. 96-110] where Dewey's own functional psychology was presented. The latter grounded his later philosophical and social psychological inquiries (like his 1917 essay «The Need for Social

Psychology» [4, p. 53-64], and especially his 1922 book Human Nature and Conduct subtitled «An Introduction to Social Psychology» [6]). Nevertheless, the origins of social psychology as a discipline officially date back to the 1930s, and especially to the 1940s [10, 22].

In this paper, I bracket the question of exactly why Dewey's approach to social psychology as an inquiry into habit is forgotten, although, we can speculate that the reason for such «forgetfulness» could be that the notion of habit has not been studied by social psychologists the way it could have, because, since the very beginning, the discipline has always had a «cognitive bend» [10, p. 30], which was especially reinforced by the appearance of the cognitive social psychology/social cognition that embraced the computer functionalist/information-processing model of the mind. And given that habits are usually considered as something «mindless»/«automatic», such neglect seems to have been justified. But if Dewey is correct in saying that the study of our habits is the actual key to the whole of the discipline of social psychology [6, p. 3], then such a neglect seems at least questionable, if not more. Especially because, it is not at all clear whether habits are purely automatic processes with no cognitive element in it.

According to social psychologist Wendy Wood [26], even though «`Habit' is largely missing» from modern social and personality psychology», there are still «signs of change», and «psychology more broadly is showing a resurgence of interest in habit» [Ibid, p. 389].

How do contemporary (social) psychologists define the phenomenon of habit itself and its essential features?

Bas Verplanken [25] argues that «there are two variants of habit definitions» [Ibid, p. 3]. On the one hand, it is an «acquired/memory¬based propensity» that can be found in works of the earlier psychologists like James, Dewey, and Veblen [Ibid]. On the other hand, habits are defined as «repeated form of conduct, or simply repeated behaviour» [Ibid]. Verplanken unites these two approaches into one and defines habit properly as «a memory-based cognitive associative entity which includes a history of behavioural repetition» [Ibid, p. 4]. According to Verplanken, behavioral repetition distinguishes habit from other cognitive representations that underlie automatic processes such as «schemas, first impressions, norms, or attributions» [Ibid]. Overall, habit has two essential features or «pillars»: (a) «a history of behavioural repetition, and (b) «a cognitive representation of an association between cues and responses» [Ibid]. Taken together and including all the history of the psychological development, Verplanken arrives at the following definition of the phenomenon: habits are «memory- based propensities to respond automatically to specific cues, which are acquired by the repetition of cue-specific behaviours in stable contexts» [Ibid].

Asaf Mazar and Wendy Wood [15] define habits in the following way: they are «cue-response associations in memory that are acquired slowly through repetition of an action in a stable circumstance» [Ibid, p. 14]. In this paper, as well as in others (e.g., Neal, Wood and Quinn [16], Wood and Pascoe [17], Wood [26]), Wood et al emphasize two main features of habits, namely their automaticity and goal-independence.

Habit automaticity entails that our habits are automatic responses that are directly activated but the situation cue/trigger. Despite the agent's intentions, habits are activated once the specific trigger shows itself. Therefore, in our habitual actions, there are no thinking or mind/cognitive processes involved. Habits are «mindless». Between the situation «sti¬mulus» and the habitual behavioral «response» there seems to be nothing cognitive. Habit is a non-cognitive process essentially. And, automatic processes are likely goal-independent because «they can function in the absence of, or even contrary to, intentions» [15, p. 17].

It seems that the contemporary understanding of habits is grounded in the stimulus-response arc. Once there is a contextual «stimulus», there comes an immediate behavioral «response». And thus, there is a direct dependence of the latter on the former. Such an approach was heavily criticized by John Dewey in his 1896 article «The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology» [2, p. 96-110], where he showed that there is no such stimulus-response arc because such an understanding is still a heritage of the religiously driven mind-body dualism. Instead, the stimulus- response schema presents itself more like a loop that is grounded in the organism's sensorimotor circuit. Elsewhere, I show that both «stimulus» and «response» are more likely to be interpretations of the functional kind that are grounded in the organism's interpretive effort. It means that the connection between a context/situation's cue/trigger and a behavioral response is not direct/immediate but rather indirect/mediate. And what it is mediated with is a functional interpretive meaning.

In fact, I will argue that even though habits appear as «automatic», they are still cognitive, and therefore, not «mindless». Habit-automaticity does not entail its mindlessness as it is usually perceived. Habits are not goal-independent but rather goal-oriented/dependent: the main goal of habit-formation is to resolve problematic situations that the organism is dealing with. Therefore, habits should be paid more attention in the social psychology, and in cognitive social psychology/social cognition, in particular.

Part 2. Charles Peirce on belief as a habit

My short introduction to Peirce's view on beliefs-as-habits will be based on his famous articles «The Fixation of Belief» [18, p. 5-22], and «How to Make Our Ideas Clear» [19, p. 23-41].

The Fixation of Belief (1877)

The goal of this paper is to clarify how we actually form and fix our beliefs, as well as «to describe the method of scientific investigation» [18, p. 19]. The thesis of the paper is to show that belief is essentially a habit, and that the best method to form a proper habit, and therefore a belief, is that of science. Thus, generally there are two «states of mind»: doubt and belief.

According to Peirce, «doubt is an uneasy and dissatisfied state from which we struggle to free ourselves and to pass into the state of belief» [18, p. 10]. The state of belief, on the other hand, is «a calm and satisfactory state which we do not wish to avoid or to change to a belief in anything else. On the contrary, we cling tenaciously, not merely to believing, but to believing just what we do believe» [Ibid]. For Peirce, both belief and doubt play rather positive roles for us. On the one hand, belief «puts us into such a condition that we shall behave in some certain way, when the occasion arises» [Ibid]. When it comes to doubt, the latter «stimulates us to inquiry until it is destroyed» [Ibid]. Therefore, it is only «the irritation of doubt [that] causes a struggle to attain a state of belief». And this very «struggle» Peirce calls «Inquiry». One has to mention that «irritation of doubt is the only immediate motive for the struggle to attain belief», while «the sole object of inquiry is the settlement of opinion» [Ibid]. To sum up, our main goal is to overcome doubt and attain a belief/habit. The latter is the consequence and the guiding principle of a doubtful situation (or the «irritation of doubt»). Our habits, which are essentially «opinions», help us eliminate doubt and stabilize the situation which appeared doubtful/problematic. Such stabilization is called «inquiry».

How to Make Our Ideas Clear (1878)

The title of the paper reflects the goal of the paper, while the thesis aims to prove that the only way to clear any idea properly is to look at the practical consequences that follow from its application. Thus, Peirce formulates the famous Pragmatic maxim:

Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object [19, p. 31].

What do practical bearings/consequences actually mean? For Peirce, the latter refer specifically to habits: «the whole function of thought is to produce habits of action» because «to develop its meaning, we have, therefore, simply to determine what habits it produces, for what a thing means is simply what habits it involves» [19, p. 30].

If belief is essentially a habit, then what is habit in itself? In Part 3 and Part 4, I am looking at the functional psychology of William James and John Dewey to find that out.

Part 3. Origins of the pragmatic understanding of habit: functional psychology of William James (1890)

William James starts Chapter IV in his seminal Principles of Psychology [9] as follows, «When we look at living creatures from an outward point of view, one of the first things that strike us is that they are bundles of habits» [Ibid, p. 104]. At the end of the same chapter, James proceeds with the same spirit, «Could the young but realize how soon they will become mere walking bundles of habits, they would give more heed to their conduct while in the plastic state» [Ibid, p. 127]. This last quote seems to be both optimistic and pessimistic at the same time.

On the one hand, it is implied that we have a «plastic state» that enables us to change. On the other hand, this state is also «time-limited»: the changes can occur only for a certain period of time. Thus, our personal habits can be «fixed» only before we are twenty. Our intellectual and professional habits can be acquired only between the age of twenty and thirty, because after the age of thirty it will be likely impossible [Ibid, p. 121-122]. Therefore, in order not to miss such a window of possibilities we «must make automatic and habitual, as early as possible, as many useful actions as we can» [Ibid, p. 124]. The latter constitutes what James calls the «ethical implications of the law of habit» [Ibid, p. 120]. Now, the quest is to clarify the meaning of the notion of «habit» itself. What is «habit?»

In what follows, I descriptively lay out James's own perspective on the phenomenon. I am specifically looking at the underlying mechanism of habit, and its function (i.e., what it does). James seems not to have provided any direct «philosophical» definition of habit, and thus, in section 3.5, I attempt to reconstruct it as well.

William James's description of habit

In Chapter IV of his Principles of Psychology, William James attempts fundamentally to describe the phenomenon, as well as to specify its essential features. As we saw, James begins the chapter with the general statement that «all living creatures» are «the bundles of habits» [Ibid, p. 104]. In wild animals, the majority of them are active from birth, and present themselves as instincts. In domesticated animals, and especially in humans, many of the habits (including some of the instincts) are usually acquired through education. And some of these would be called «acts of reason». In anyway, habits constitute a huge part of our lives, and therefore they should be clarified in the first place. From the very beginning, James does not give a precise definition of what a habit actually is. He rather starts with what it is due. Or, in other words, what makes the emergence of the phenomenon possible.

What makes habits possible?

For James, even the laws of nature are nothing but «immutable habits». When the habits of nature are «immutable», the habits of living organisms are «mutable». Thus, the line of the difference between the habits of nature and those of the living creatures lies in the latter's ability to change or «plasticity». The latter, according to James, «in the wide sense of the word, means the possession of a structure weak enough to yield to an influence, but strong enough not to yield all at once. Each relatively stable phase of equilibrium in such a structure is marked by what we may call a new set of habits» [Ibid, p. 105]. The organic matter (especially the nervous tissue) has the «extraordinary degree of plasticity». Therefore, what makes the phenomenon of habit in the living organisms possible is due to the «plasticity of the organic materials of which their bodies are composed» [Ibid]. It especially includes the «brain-matter» and the «spinal cord» [Ibid, p. 107]. Following that, James confesses that the «philosophy of habit is thus, in the first instance, a chapter in physics rather than in physiology or psychology» [Ibid, p. 105].

The function of habit, or what it does

The function of habit is grounded in its «philosophy» from which one can specify a particular law or the «law of habit». The latter James understands as the following principle: «our nervous system grows to the modes in which it has been exercised» [Ibid, p. 112]. According to James, we can specify the following habit functions.

«Habit simplifies the movements required to achieve a given result, makes them more accurate and diminishes fatigue» [Ibid]. As James also puts it, «man is born with a tendency to do more things» than the capacity of his «nerve-centres» allows. The majority of actions in animals are automatic, but when it comes to a man, the «number of them is so enormous that most of them must be the fruit of painful studies» [Ibid, p. 213]. The moral is that habits make one's life less painful.

«Habit diminishes the conscious attention with which our acts are performed» [Ibid, p. 114]. In our voluntary actions, e.g., when we learn something, our actions are made through trial and error. In such process, «we interrupt ourselves at every step by unnecessary movements and false notes» [Ibid]. But when they are «proficient», our activities require «the very minimum of muscular action requisite to bring them forth, they also follow from a single instantaneous `cue'» [Ibid].

The mechanism of habit as a «sensorimotor zigzag»

According to James,

In action grown habitual, what instigates each new muscular contraction to take place in its appointed order is not through a thought or a perception, but the sensation occasioned by the muscular contraction just finished [Ibid, p. 115].

«A strictly voluntary act» is solely guided by an «idea, perception, and volition», but when it comes to the habitual action «the mere sensation is a sufficient guide» [Ibid].

The diagram below represents the mechanism of habit.

«V» symbolizes the «command to start». The latter can be a thought, or a «mere perception», etc. «Symbols «À», «Â», «Ñ», «D», «Å», «F», «G» signify «an habitual chain of muscular contractions». And the «G'» represents the «intellectual perception» which is the effect of G. Symbols «a», «b», «c», «d», «e», «f» represent the «sensations» that the former muscular contractions «excite». [Ibid, p. 116-117].

It is interesting that, on the one hand, James claims that the sensations are «occasioned by the muscular contractions just finished» [Ibid, p. 115], while on the other hand, he calls «a», «b», «c», «d», «e», «f» the «antecedents of the successive muscular attractions» [my emphasis] [Ibid, p. 117] which in themselves are «immediate» [Ibid, p. 118], and as such are accompanied by the consciousness of some sort that is «usually inattentive» and which comes to our attention if sensations go wrong.

The above-shown diagram suggests labeling the mechanism of habit as the «sensorimotor zigzag». But the description of the mechanism is not clear. On the one hand, James seems to be trapped in the psychological fallacy that Dewey would later label the «reflex arc concept» that is predicated on the idea that the motor «response» is always preceded by the sensory «stimulus».

On the other hand, it also seems that James is not very much consistent in that, he says that the sensations are «occasioned by the muscular contractions just finished» which suggests that it is the motor response that comes first. It is also possible that, such inconsistency can be interpreted as the «proto state» of what Dewey would later call the «sensorimotor circuit».

What is habit?

Even though James himself tends to define the phenomenon of habit reductively (i.e., as a plasticity of the organic matter, and especially that of the brain and the spinal cord), one can still find a more «philosophical» understanding of the phenomenon in the chapter. It can be found when James is linking the following phenomena: that of the «habit» with those of the «character», and of the «will». Thus, «a character is a completely fashioned will» [Ibid, p. 125]. The latter James interprets as «an aggregate of tendencies to act in a firm and prompt and definite way upon all the principal emergencies of life» [Ibid]. And, that «tendency to act only becomes effectively ingrained in us in proportion to the uninterrupted frequency with which the actions actually occur, and the brain `grows' to their use» [Ibid].

Here, the phenomenon of habit is not being reductively explained, but rather there is something else that corresponds to when the «brain `grows'». One can see that this «something else» is a «tendency to act» that is characterized by its being «firm», «prompt», and exercised in a «definite way». Another feature of this action is to be «frequent», and «uninterrupted». I think that this is a real «philosophical» definition of the phenomenon of habit that one can find in the analyzed chapter 4 of James's Principles.

In other words, habit is one's constant disposition/inclination to act. What is the origin of such a disposition? In the next part, I argue that such a constant disposition/«tendency» to act is essentially pragmatic - hermeneutic in its origin.

Part 4. A pragmatic-hermeneutic approach to the phenomenon of habit

In this part, I extend James's approach to the phenomenon of habit from what I would call the «pragmatic-hermeneutic approach». In what follows, I am arguing that (1) the phenomenon of habit should be seen as a «`fixed' functional interpretation of the world and one's place in it that either works or does not work», which in itself constitutes whether this or that habit is a «good» habit or a «bad» one. (2) Habits are essentially normative, and their normativity is «two-dimensional»: habits are norms, and, as such, they are subjects to (other) norms.

Dewey's functional psychology of 1896

One can say that our relation to the world is essentially grounded in our sensorimotor activity which in itself is grounded in what John Dewey [2] called the sensorimotor circuit. The core idea is that «stimuli» (understood as «sensations») and «responses» (conceived as «motor movements») do not form the «arc» in which the stimulus always comes first, and the response always comes second, but that the relation between them should be reinterpreted rather as a circuit. Thus, in this sense, it can be that the response/movement comes «first», and the stimulus/sensation comes «second». The stimulus is interpreted as «stimulus» only within the movement/response. Thus, stimulus and response are functional parts of the functional whole of the sensorimotor circuit. In [14], I show that in his groundbreaking article, Dewey suggests that both stimulus and response are basically functional interpretations. An organism interprets a sensory stimulus as «stimulus», and the movement/response as «response» in terms of their functional roles in resolving the problematic situation that the organism is dealing with. Therefore, my claim is that an organism always makes an interpretive effort to recognize these functional parts of the functional whole of the sensorimotor circuit.

What was the «stimulus» in one situation can become a «response» in the other situation, and vice versa. This allows us to reinterpret Dewey's «immediate empiricism» as rather the «hermeneutic empiri¬cism», the motto of which, instead of the classical «things are what they are experienced as», would be rather «things are what they are interpreted as»/«things are experienced what they are interpreted as» [Ibid]. Therefore, we always start with interpretations, and end with interpretations. Now, how does this fit into the discussion of habit?

A habit is a «fixed» functional interpretation that either works or does not work

Generally speaking, there are two kinds of habits. «Good» habits and «bad» habits. What constitutes this or that habit as a «good» habit, and what constitutes this or that habit as a «bad» habit? First, I think that habit is a «good» one if it is interpreted as a «good» habit. And similarly, a habit is seen as a «bad» habit, if it is interpreted as a «bad» habit. The «as» part here refers to the meaning that is grounded in one's interpretation of the event, or in other words, the interpretive meaning. If good/bad habits are interpretations, then what differentiates a «good» interpretation from a «bad» interpretation?

First, by a «good» interpretation I mean what can be called as the «correct»/«true» interpretation, and by the «bad» interpretation I understand the «incorrect»/«false» interpretation. What is the main difference between them? What makes the difference here is whether this or that interpretation actually works. Pragmatically speaking, for an interpretation to «work» would mean to correspond to the «facts» of the present situation. That is, an interpretation works if (i) it successfully/«correctly» identifies the problematic/unstable situation as problematic/unstable one; and (ii) if it helps successfully to resolve such a situation into a nonproblematic/stable one respectively.

A «good» habit presents itself as a «fixed» functional interpretation that actually works. Through repetitive installment and practicing, it was eventually determined that this particular way of an organism's interaction with the environment resolves the problematic and unstable situation into the unproblematic and stable one, and that is how it becomes «automatic». By analogy, a «bad» habit is grounded in the organism's specific interpretation that does not work. Such an interpretation usually only seems to work (like the habit of smoking) when it does not in fact. In other words, it is largely an illusion/delusion that every time when the habit in question is being activated, the problem has been interpreted as «solved», while in reality, it has been not.

Therefore, habits are «fixed» functional interpretations that either work or do not work, which determines whether the habits in question are «good» or «bad».

Habit and normativity

As we saw, in his Principles, James advises acquiring as many good habits and getting rid of as many bad habits as possible, and as early as possible. Why is that so? It is because good habits will eventually and necessarily help a person to succeed in his life, while bad habits would rather lead one to failure. Thus, habits in themselves are standards for success or failure, and therefore, are essentially normative. Let's explore this dimension a bit more.

Two-dimensional normativity of habits

The two-dimensional normative functioning of habits can be seen in this way. What is meant by «norm» here is some specific «fixed» functional interpretation that is a standard for success (in case of a habit being «good») or failure (in case of a habit being «bad»). Habits are norms, and as such, they are also subjects to other norms.

Let the phenomenon of «smoking cigarettes» be our example. Among a group of teenagers smoking cigarettes is usually considered as «cool». Thus, persons who smoke are «cool», and the ones who do not, are «not cool». But when a teenager encounters a social situation where such behavior is prohibited, the normative habit of his group («smoking is `cool'») becomes a subject to the norms of that social situation. For example, this teenager comes to a cafe where smoking is not allowed. If smoking is a standard for «success» (e.g., respect and admiration) within a close circle of his friends, it is a standard for «failure» when it comes to such a person's visiting a cafe that has a rule, expressed by a sign «No smoking» (such «failure», e.g., would be expressed in a possibility to be kicked out from there, etc.).

Mind engineering is culture engineering

Finally, how does the said above help us understand ourselves better? According to James, living organisms are basically «bundles of habits». We, as human beings, are cultural beings. But what is «culture»? According to

Merriam-Webster Dictionary, culture is (1) «the beliefs, customs, arts, etc., of a particular society, group, place, or time», (2) «a particular society that has its own beliefs, ways of life, art, etc». The keywords here are «beliefs» and «customs». One can say that «culture» is a set of beliefs/customs. Earlier, we identified belief as a habit. Also, it will not be a mistake to say that a «custom» is essentially a habit as well. Therefore, culture is a set of habits.

It seems that both «mind» and «culture» have the same predicate, i.e., a «set of habits». This suggests not only that mind is culture but shows that mind engineering is also «culture engineering».

What role do cultural habits play in a person's life? I think that essentially culture helps one interpret the world and find one's place in it. Thus, we can also extend our definition of habits as «fixed» functional interpretations of the world, and one's place in it that either work (good habits) or do not work (bad habits). Therefore, mind/culture is a set of «fixed» functional interpretations of the world and one's place in it that either work («good» mind/culture) or do not work («bad» mind/culture).

In the end, studying our habits, and those of others is the key to understanding ourselves, others, and our mutual relationship in and with the world. As Dewey wrote in his Human Nature and Conduct, «Man is a creature of habit, not of reason nor yet of instinct» [6, p. 88].

Part 5. Reinterpretation of mind engineering as habit engineering

Let's go back to our initial definition of mind engineering. Earlier, I defined it as a process of the «design/redesign, implementation/reimplementation and evaluation/reevaluation of minds». Since the mind is considered a «set of habits», then mind engineering is happily transformed into habit engineering. Now, how does that very process of habit engineering take place overall?

A stream of habit

In his Principles, William James claimed that when it comes to our consciousness, it is like a «stream» which leads to his famous metaphor «stream of consciousness». I want to borrow James's expression where instead of «consciousness» I will use «habit». The outcome is a «stream of habit».

When an organism is in its «peace of mind», its habits are still and not interrupted. That is where the organism's routine is stable and continuous. An organism and the contextual whole of a situation that it is in seem to be inseparable. That is where things «work», and its equilibrium is stable, and its habits are «fixed». A problem arises when the contextual whole of a situation becomes problematic. How does the latter occur? According to Dewey, it is when «something happens» [7, p. 13]. When it does the organism's «fixed» functional interpretations of the world are shaken and, as a result, its «stream of habit» is violated. I think, this signifies the exact start of mind/habit-engineering to take place.

Deliberate mind engineering and pragmatic method

I think that, overall, deliberate mind/habit engineering corresponds to what Dewey called a denotative method [7]/pattern of inquiry[8], or what Karl Popper called a hypothetic-deductive method.

Thus, the process of deliberate mind/habit engineering can be portrayed in the following way:

Let's look at this scheme closer.

The problematic situation comes first. In order to distinguish facts from it, we need initial hypothesis. After testing it, we come up with the conclusive hypothesis and identify facts as facts. Namely, with the application of the secondary experience, we identify primary experience as primary (i.e., what led us to the secondary experience). But if there was no secondary experience before, there would be no possibility to identify the primary experience as such [Ibid, p. 19].

In [14], I have suggested that what Dewey called «primary experience» and «secondary experience» in themselves are functional interpretations that are grounded in the organism's interpretive effort of the contextual whole of a situation that is problematic. From this, it should become clearer what I mean by «design», «implementation», and «evaluation» of habits.

Essential structure of deliberate mind/habit engineering

When it comes to deliberate mind/habit engineering we have the following constituents: (1) problematic situation, (2) design/redesign, (3) implementation/reimplementation, (4) evaluation/revaluation. We have already shared an understanding of (1), and so, now we can jump to the clarification of its other constituents.

Thus, by «design», I understand a very interpretation/hypothesis formation that arises out of one's interpretive effort which in itself is an act that is grounded in the organism's sensorimotor circuit. The «design» is a process of interpretation/hypothesis-forming where an organism interprets a problem as a problem, and develops a further interpretation (hypothesis) to actually «fix» it.

By «implementation» then is meant nothing but an experiment, or a hypothesis-testing. That is a process when this or that hypothesis/interpre¬tation that is about to solve/fix the very problem is being tested.

«Evaluation» refers to the end-result of the hypothesis-testing. That is, if a hypothesis/interpretation works (i.e., if it correctly identifies the problem and successfully constantly resolves/fixes it), then it essentially becomes a «good» habit. And, if it does not work (e.g., if it just seems to resolve the problematic situation when it does not in fact), then such a hypothesis/interpretation is a candidate for becoming a «bad» habit respectively.

The prefix «re» applies in all cases when there is a need either to «redesign», or to «reform» a specific interpretation of the problematic si¬tuation (in case the facts have changed), and then to «reimplement»/retest such an interpretation/hypothesis experimentally through what Dewey would call «doing and making», and Popper signified as «trial and error» process, and, in the end, to «reevaluate» the outcome whether it works or not. When it does, such an interpretation becomes «fixed» and successfully enacts one's relation to the world and their place in it. If not, the process of such «engineering» needs to be repeated.

Therefore, the process of deliberate mind engineering can be summari¬zed in the following way.

Design/Redesign: hypothesis-formation/reformation (interpreting/ reinterpreting the problem as a problem).

Implementation/Reimplementation: experimental testing/retesting hypotheses (as habit-candidates).

Evaluation/Reevaluation of hypotheses/interpretations as to whether they work (i.e., correctly identify and successfully resolve a problematic situation) or not. Reevaluation of a habit leads either to its redesign and reimplementation, or its further elimination and coming up with a better one instead.

Are habits cognitive?

As we saw earlier,12 in social psychology habits are usually understood as mindless/automatic processes. But if our mind is essentially a set of habits, and our habits are «mindless» then it would lead to a conclusion that our «mind is mindless», and that we are «mindless creatures», or basically «zombies», which would simply be absurd. Therefore, there is either a problem with the very definition of the mind as it has been employed here, or there is a real problem with the understanding of habit as a mindless process. I think that it is rather the latter. Indeed, if the mind is a set of habits, and habits are essentially «fixed» functional interpretations of the world that are grounded in an organism's interpretive effort, then it would seem to imply that habits are not just purely automatic but cognitive as well. But how cognitive? What is «cognitive»?

Cognition: ordinary definition vs. scientific definition

Merriam-Webster primarily defines cognitive as «of, relating to, being, or involving conscious intellectual activity (such as thinking, reasoning, or remembering)».13 Cambridge Dictionary refers to cognitive as «connected with thinking or conscious mental processes».14 Collins defines cognitive as «relating to the mental process involved in knowing, learning, and understanding things».15

APA defines cognition as «all forms of knowing and awareness, such as perceiving, conceiving, remembering, reasoning, judging, imagining, and problem solving. Along with affect and conation, it is one of the three traditionally identified components of mind».

It seems that both the ordinary and scientific definitions of cognitive appeal to it as mainly an intellectual activity.

In [14] I made a distinction between two kinds of cognitive: «weakly» cognitive and «strongly» cognitive. The former refers to the interpretive effort of the organism that is grounded in its sensorimotor circuit. The «strongly» cognitive means an intellectual activity. Thus, it seems that the definitions of cognitive as shown above are primarily reductive because they narrow down its meaning only to the «strong» sense of the cognitive while leaving the «weak» sense of it out of the picture.

Habits are «fixed» functional interpretations. The latter (i.e., interpretations) in themselves can be both «weakly» and «strongly» cognitive. Therefore, we can also extend the cognitive meaning of habits to two. On the one hand, habits are «weakly» cognitive simply because even in our ordinary routine we make an interpretive effort. Thus, when we make and then drink our morning coffee, we have to interpret a coffeemaker as a coffeemaker, and a coffee cup as a coffee cup. There is nothing much intellectual about such routine but despite that we still have habitually but interpret, and therefore, cognize the above-mentioned things as to what they are. If, say, we suddenly started to interpret a table not as a table but as a coffeemaker, our morning coffee-drinking routine would have failed.

But when dealing with intellectual activities, it is possible to say that we have our intellectual habits as well. Thus, when working on some logical proofs, we, say, have habitually to apply modus ponens and/or modus tollens rules of inferences. To be successful in this kind of activity, it would be a mistake to affirm the consequent in case of modus ponens, and to deny the antecedent in case of modus tollens. For a logic practitioner, such routine would be habitual (because it would be a constant pain to learn it anew every time, say, by analogy with the protagonist from Memento). Nevertheless, even if such a process is habitual (i.e., «automatic»), it still does not cease to be intellectual. Therefore, habits are not just «mindless» (i.e., non-cognitive) automatic processes. In fact, they are essentially cognitive in both «weak» and «strong» senses of the word (depending on the situation). Therefore, the automaticity of habits does not entail their mindlessness or their being non-cognitive.

Mind engineering and social organization

It seems clear that deliberate mind-engineering requires an agent- environment interaction. It is not just one way but essentially a two¬way street. To experimentally test one's interpretations/hypotheses one necessarily needs a feedback loop with the environment. It is simply impossible to really check whether this or that hypothesis works, if there is no testing or checking.

This suggests that when it comes to the phenomenon of forceful mind engineering or «brainwashing», the situation is totally different. Since by mind engineering, we mean essentially habit engineering, then «brai- nwashing»/forceful mind engineering can be described as a habitwashing respectively.

How can we explain the phenomenon of forceful mind engineering or «brainwashing?» What are its essential features?

Kathleen Taylor [24] defines brainwashing as a «dream of controlling other people's beliefs and behaviour so effectively that they do not feel manipulated--as if the imposed beliefs were their own» [Ibid, p.viii] that she reduces to three kinds, «by force, by stealth, and by direct brain manipulation technologies» [Ibid, p. xiii] as well as specifies the following essential features that constitute the phenomenon: isolation, control, uncertainty, repetition and emotional manipulation.

Thus, she writes:

The aim is to isolate victims from their previous environment; control what they perceive, think, and do; increase uncertainty about previous beliefs; instil new beliefs by repetition; and employ positive and negative emotions to weaken former beliefs and strengthen new ones (Collectively, these can be labelled `ICURE' techniques.) In brainwashing by force, ICURE techniques are taken to the coercive extremes found in some cults and terrorist organisations» [Ibid, p.xiii].

This suggests that what we termed as deliberate mind-engineering can essentially be realized largely in free, open or democratic societies. It is important to notice that both Dewey and Popper were theoreticians of democracies and were direct critics and opponents of autocracies and totalitarianisms. According to Dewey, the essence of democracy is what one can call a participatory democracy [2, p. xx], [5, p. xxiv], where «democracy was not only a political form of government but a way of life» [5, p. xxiv]. In such a system there is indeed an above-mentioned agent-environment «feedback loop». An «agent» in this case is an ordinary citizen or the powers that be while their «environment» is a society that they are part of. Therefore, on a social scale, the essential condition for the genuine (i.e., deliberate) mind-engineering is a democratic system of government and social organization where there is both a top-to-down (i.e., powers that be ^ citizens) and a down-to-top (i.e., citizens ^ powers that be) transaction. This represents the normal state of democratic affairs as well as the natural (i.e., experimental) way to «fix» one's interpretations of the world and one's place in it (i.e., a natural way to make habits). Such a «fixation» is essentially a fallibilist one, i.e., the one that is able to be criticized and disproved at any moment when the facts suggest so. As Charles Peirce put it, «The best that can be done is to supply a hypothesis, not devoid of all likelihood, in the general line of growth of scientific ideas, and capable of being verified or refuted by future observers», because «the first step toward finding out is to acknowledge you do not satisfactorily know already» [20, p. 2, 4].


Ïîäîáíûå äîêóìåíòû

  • Äåôîëòíàÿ ñåòü ìîçãà. Ïîçèòèâíûå è íåãàòèâíûå ñòîðîíû mind-wandering. Ôîðìèðîâàíèå âîñïîìèíàíèé "áðîäÿùåãî ðàçóìà". Ýêñïåðèìåíòàëüíûå èññëåäîâàíèÿ ñ òî÷êè çðåíèÿ êîãíèòèâíîé íåéðîíàóêè. Ýìîöèè è íàñòðîåíèå. Ñîçíàíèå è ïñèõè÷åñêîå ïóòåøåñòâèå âî âðåìåíè.

    êîíòðîëüíàÿ ðàáîòà [27,1 K], äîáàâëåí 05.05.2014

  • The definition of conformism as passive acceptance and adaptation to standards of personal conduct, rules and regulations of the cult of absolute power. Study the phenomenon of group pressure. External and internal views of subordination to the group.

    ðåôåðàò [15,3 K], äîáàâëåí 14.05.2011

  • The essence of an environmental problem. Features of global problems. Family, poverty, war and peace problems. Culture and moral crisis. Global problems is invitation to the human mind. Moral and philosophical priorities in relationship with the nature.

    ðåôåðàò [41,3 K], äîáàâëåí 25.04.2014

  • Îáùàÿ èíôîðìàöèÿ î Siemens Teamcenter Engineering. Ñîñòàâíûå ÷àñòè ïðèëîæåíèÿ "Ìîé íàâèãàòîð". Èçìåíåíèÿ â êîíñòðóêöèè êðûëà ÈË-76ÌÄ-90À. Ìîäåðíèçèðîâàíèå òîïëèâíîé ñèñòåìû ñàìîëåòà, ìîäåëèðîâàíèå êîìïåíñàòîðà â Unigraphics NX. Èçìåíåíèå ìàòåðèàëà.

    êîíòðîëüíàÿ ðàáîòà [1,0 M], äîáàâëåí 27.05.2014

  • Approach - one’s viewpoint toward teaching. The set of principles, beliefs, or ideas about the nature of learning which is translated into the classroom. Learner, performance and competency based approach. Teacher’s and student’s role in the teaching.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [447,5 K], äîáàâëåí 21.10.2015

  • Estimate risk-neutral probabilities and the rational for its application. Empirical results of predictive power assessment for risk-neutral probabilities as well as their comparisons with stock-implied probabilities defined as in Samuelson and Rosenthal.

    äèïëîìíàÿ ðàáîòà [549,4 K], äîáàâëåí 02.11.2015

  • The role of mass media in modern life. The influence of newspapers, magazines and television in mind and outlook of the mass of people. Ways to provide information and display the news of dramatic events, natural disasters, plane crash, murders and wars.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [730,5 K], äîáàâëåí 17.05.2011

  • 8 bad habits that reduce youth and life. Effect of nicotine to the brain, nervous system and the associated excess sweating. The composition of tobacco smoke. Closely relation of sport and health. The harm of smoking for women, the human psyche.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [777,7 K], äîáàâëåí 07.11.2014

  • Ïðîòîòèï èíòåðôåéñîâ ïðîãðàììû. Mind map äèàãðàììà. Ïîëèòèêà ðåàëèçàöèè áåçîïàñíîñòè è ñîõðàííîñòè äàííûõ. Áëîê-ñõåìà ðåàëèçàöèè ôóíêöèîíàëà ïðîãðàììû. Ôîðìà, èíòåðôåéñ ëè÷íîãî êàáèíåòà ïîëüçîâàòåëÿ. Ïðîâåðêè âî âðåìÿ çàïîëíåíèÿ ðåãèñòðàöèîííîé ôîðìû.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [3,3 M], äîáàâëåí 14.09.2016

  • Control the doctors’ prescriptions. Microchip in Blood Pressure Pills Nags Patients Who Skip Meds. Microchip implants linked to cancer in animal. Microchip Implants, Mind Control, and Cybernetics. Some about VeriChip. TI microchip technology in medicine.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [732,8 K], äîáàâëåí 12.01.2012

Ðàáîòû â àðõèâàõ êðàñèâî îôîðìëåíû ñîãëàñíî òðåáîâàíèÿì ÂÓÇîâ è ñîäåðæàò ðèñóíêè, äèàãðàììû, ôîðìóëû è ò.ä.
PPT, PPTX è PDF-ôàéëû ïðåäñòàâëåíû òîëüêî â àðõèâàõ.
Ðåêîìåíäóåì ñêà÷àòü ðàáîòó.