How could husserl’s theory of the bodily self-constitution of the ego help bridge the explanatory gap?

The present paper endeavours to show how Husserl’s theory of the bodily self-constitution of the ego could help us, not to close the explanatory gap in a reductionist manner, but rather to bridge this gap by rendering apparent the necessary connection.

Рубрика Философия
Вид статья
Язык английский
Дата добавления 02.10.2024
Размер файла 62,8 K

Отправить свою хорошую работу в базу знаний просто. Используйте форму, расположенную ниже

Студенты, аспиранты, молодые ученые, использующие базу знаний в своей учебе и работе, будут вам очень благодарны.

A crucial component of our train of thought was that according to Husserl one can only conceive of a particular phenomenon in a concrete manner by considering the wider web of meanings and other phenomena in which the phenomenon in question is embedded. Constitution means to follow the a priori necessary connection between phenomena and meanings “A priori” here means not only formal a priori like “there is no father without at least one child,” but also material a priori, so, judgments like “there is no colour without extension” (cf. Husserl, 2002a, II, 134).. Furthermore, it is Husserl's opinion that certain phenomena, especially those that are connected to perception and the appearance of physical reality, necessarily carry an indication to extra-mental transcendence in themselves. In his eyes, if we abstract from the indication to transcendent reality in those phenomena, we just do not have their concrete, proper meaning, we only have an abstract, inadequate, impoverished aspect of them See footnote 32 earlier..

Concerning consciousness as such and ego, Husserl believes that these phenomena necessarily, intrinsically, and in an a priori way imply a wide, coherent context of other phenomena. We just do not have their adequate, proper conception without that wider web. For example, we can imagine a sheer visual image without a perceiving subject or visual organs, or we can also imagine an animate experiencing locomotive as Husserl did in Ideas III (Husserl, 1980, 104), or a speaking, feeling, experiencing teapot as in Disney cartoons-but in Husserl's idea these would have just been inadequate conceptions of phenomena that we wantonly ripped out of their wider context. In Husserl's view, a subjective conscious capability refers to other subjective capabilities: it indicates a whole system of mental structures and abilities. This system refers to a whole way of life in a physical world, and thus also implies physical embodiment (Korperlichkeit), and not just the experience of embodiment (Leiblichkeit). “Concrete consciousness” means that a subject's mental sphere can only be conceived of as concrete, as an organic, coherent system of mental capabilities, structures, and contents, which refer to their embodied, corporeal aspect, and a concrete way of life in the external, physical world. It is an illusion to think that we can grasp an individual mental capability or experience on its own, independently from everything, from other mental capabilities and experiences, embodiment, and transcendent reality, in a phenomenologically full, adequate and accurate manner. Especially according to the later Husserl, in the 1930s, if we think we did so we did not pay enough attention to the phenomena themselves In the 1930s it was Husserl's opinion that we cannot suspend or “put out of play” („Aufer Spiel setzenf a whole world-horizon or world-context without re-enacting or re-establishing a new world-horizon or world-context (cf. Husserl, 2008a, 251-258). (“The apodictic certainty of my hu-man-bodily being as part of the apodictic certainty of the Being-foundation of `world.' Rejection of the Cartesian skeptical attempt.”).

We attempted to show that the self-constitution of the ego, the process through which the transcendental ego conceives and apperceives itself as an embodied, flesh and bone human person in the world, as a partly empirical and physical entity, cannot be entirely arbitrary, not even in a priori terms. This process has a priori necessary features, which also has certain, distinguishable layers. The transcendental ego necessarily constitutes itself as an organic subject with an organic body, whose organs enable it to have access to, and to perform different actions in, the world, and the constitution of the organic body also embraces the constitution of a “central organ” whose constitutive role is to coordinate the functioning of all other organs, and integrate them into a coherent system. In Husserl's opinion, even the constitution of an animate, experiencing subject cannot entirely be contingent.

In this regard, it was of fundamental importance for us how empirical, natural scientific knowledge can be used under the phenomenological reduction, in a phenomenologically legitimate way. Regarding this, we emphasized two strongly related motifs. Firstly, the idea of “double phenomenological reduction” which--in our read- ing--could be used to phenomenologically clarify and re-integrate empirical findings under the phenomenological reduction. Secondly, we claimed that at a certain point of phenomenological investigations the difference between ideal and real or motivated possibilities could be relativized. At first look it might appear that this is a fixed and immovable difference. An ideal possibility is that which does not contain a logical contradiction and could be imagined in general. Such as an experiencing locomotive, a speaking, singing, and dancing teapot, or an experiencing, feeling subject without a body (such as a ghost). A real or motivated possibility is motivated by experiences-- such that the sun will rise tomorrow again. The boundaries however, between ideal and real possibilities are not entirely fixed, and especially genetic phenomenological analysis could help us revising them See footnote 38.. Motivated possibilities could disclose their a priori, necessary features under a closer phenomenological analysis, and they could reinterpret in a phenomenologically legitimate manner, as having partly ideal moments, and could partly be considered as ideal possibilities See footnote 45..

We tried to make it plausible that these considerations could make a substantial contribution to handling the problem of explanatory gap, particularly from a phenomenological viewpoint, in a twofold way. Epistemologically, through the internal, immanent analysis of subjective experiences, one can systematically unfold and map the peculiar context of other immanent phenomena and meanings, and one can identify and follow up the indications in these experiences to structures of embodiment and transcendent reality. In this manner, this immanently oriented, Husserlian project could orient empirical research into the essence of consciousness and its bodily basis. Ontologically, one can also use Husserl's assumptions on mind-body relationship, and one can also articulate a standpoint concerning this latter matter, depending how seriously one takes Husserl's idealistic commitments From time-to-time Husserl makes statements that explicitly indicate that Husserl could be con-sidered as a whole-hearted dualist. He speculates about the immortality of the transcendental ego, he refers to the transcendental ego in terms of a “transcendental substance,” which is absolutely independent from the material body, and also from physical, natural reality itself. (Husserl, 2006b, 176-177). It would be the topic of another essay to have a closer look at how Husserl attempted to justify such claims.. This latter problem, however, is a topic of another study.

Acknowledgements: First of all, I would like to express my gratitude to my two reviewers. Their helpful, encouraging, and supportive remarks really helped me to make a significantly improved version of the original manuscript. I also would like to say thank you very much to Christoph Durt, Todd Feinberg, Samuel Fawcett, Jon Mallatt, and Jeffrey Yoshimi.

REFERENCES

1. Behnke, E. (2011). Edmund Husserl: Phenomenology of Embodiment. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/husspemb/

2. Blackmore, S. (2017). Untestable Claims and the Evolution of Consciousness. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 32 (5), 311-312.

3. Breuer, I. (2017). Aristotle and Husserl on the Relationship between the Necessity of a Fact and Contingency. In New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, XV (269-296). London: Routledge.

4. Broad, C. D. (1925). The Mind and Its Place in Nature. New York: Harcourt, Brace & Company, Inc.

5. Chalmers, D. (1995). Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2 (3), 200-219.

6. Chalmers, D. (1996). The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

7. Churchland, P.S. (1996). The Hornswoggle Problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3 (5-6), 402408.

8. Claesges, U. (1964). Edmund Husserls Theorie der Raumkonstitution. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

9. Clark, A. (2008). Pressing the Flesh: A Tension in the Study of the Embodied, Embedded Mind? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76 (1), 37-59.

10. Cobb-Stevens, R. (1990). Husserl and Analytic Philosophy. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

11. Cosmelli, D., & Thompson, E. (2010). Embodiment or Envatment? Reflections on the Bodily Basis of Consciousness. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction. Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science (361-386). Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

12. Dahlstrom, D. O., Elpidorou, A., & Hopp, W (Eds.). (2016). Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology. Conceptual and Empirical Approaches. London & New York: Routledge.

13. Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.

14. Dennett, D. C. (1996). Facing Backwards on the Problem of Consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3 (1), 4-6.

15. Dreyfus, H. L. (Ed.). (1982). Husserl, Intentionality and Cognitive Science. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

16. Feinberg, T. E., & Mallatt, J. (2016). Ancient Origins of Consciousness. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

17. Feinberg, T. E., & Mallatt, J. (2018). Consciousness Demystified. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

18. Feinberg, T. E., & Mallatt, J. (2019). Subjectivity “Demystified”: Neurobiology, Evolution, and the Explanatory Gap. Frontiers in Psychology, 10. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.01686

19. Feinberg, T. E., & Mallatt, J. (2020). Phenomenal Consciousness and Emergence: Eliminating the Explanatory Gap. Frontiers in Psychology, 11. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01041

20. Fink, E. (1966). Studien zur Phdnomenologie. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

21. Fuchs, T. (2018). Ecology of the Brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

22. Fuchs, T. (2020). The Circularity of the Embodied Mind. Frontiers in Psychology, 11. https://doi. org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01707

23. Fuchs, T. (2021). In Defence of Human Being. Foundational Questions of an Embodied Anthropology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

24. Gallagher, S. (1997). Mutual Enlightenment: Recent Phenomenology in Cognitive Science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4 (3), 195-214.

25. Gallagher, S. (2011). Interpretations of Embodied Cognition. In W Tschacher & C. Bergomi (Eds.), The Implications of Embodiment: Cognition and Communication (59-71). Exeter: Imprint Academy.

26. Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The Phenomenological Mind. An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science. London & New York: Routledge.

27. Ginsburg, S., & Jablonka, E. (2019). The Evolution of the Sensitive Soul. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

28. Godfrey-Smith, P. (2019). Evolving Across the Explanatory Gap. Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology, 11 (1), 1-13.

29. Goldinger, S. D., Papesh, M. H., Barnhart, A. S., Hansen, W. A., & Hout, M. C. (2016). The Poverty of Embodied Cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 23, 959-978.

30. Heidegger, M. (2001). Being and Time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

31. Held, K. (1966). Lebendige Gegenwart. Die Frage nach der Seinsweise des transzendentalen Ich bei Edmund Husserl, entwickelt am Leitfaden der Zeitproblematik. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

32. Hurley, S., & Мсё, A. (2003). Neural Plasticity and Consciousness. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 131-168.

33. Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian Meditations. An Introduction to Phenomenology (D. Cairns, Trans.). Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

34. Husserl, E. (1970). The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. (D. Carr, Trans.). Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.

35. Husserl, E. (1973a). Zur Phdnomenologie der Intersubjektivitdt. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster Teil. 1905-1920 (Hua XIII). Den Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

36. Husserl, E. (1973b). Zur Phdnomenologie der Intersubjektivitdt. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Zweiter Teil. 1921-1928 (Hua XIV). Den Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

37. Husserl, E. (1973c). Zur Phdnomenologie der Intersubjektivitdt. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil. 1929-1935 (Hua XV). Den Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

38. Husserl, E. (1977). Phenomenological Psychology. Lectures, Summer Semester, 1925 (J. Scanlon, Trans.). Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

39. Husserl, E. (1980). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Third Book. Phenomenology and the Foundation of the Sciences (T. Klein & W. Pohl, Trans.). Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

40. Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. First Book. General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology (F Kersten, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

41. Husserl, E. (1989a). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Second Book. Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution (R. Rojcewicz & A. Schuwer, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

42. Husserl, E. (1989b). Aufsdtze und Vortrdge. 1922-1937 (Hua XXVII). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

43. Husserl, E. (1997). Thing and Space: Lectures of 1907 (R. Rojcewicz, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

44. Husserl, E. (1999). The Idea of Phenomenology (L. Hardy, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

45. Husserl, E. (2001). Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis. Lectures on Transcendental Logic (A. Steinbock, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

46. Husserl, E. (2002a). Logical Investigation I-II (J. N. Findlay, Trans.). London & New York: Routledge.

47. Husserl, E. (2002b). Zur phdnomenologischen Reduktion. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1926-1935) (Hua XXXIV). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

48. Husserl, E. (2006a). The Basic Problems of Phenomenology. From the Lectures, Winter Semester, 19101911 (I. Farin & J. G. Hart, Trans.). Dordrecht: Springer.

49. Husserl, E. (2006b). Spdte Texte tiber Zeitkonstitution (1929-1934). Die C-Manuskripte (Hua VIII) New York: Springer.

50. Husserl, E. (2008a). Die Lebenswelt. Auslegungen der vorgegebenen Welt und ihrer Konstitution. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1916-1937) (Hua XXXIX). New York: Springer.

51. Husserl, E. (2008b). Introduction to Logic and Theory of Knowledge. Lectures 1906/07 (C. O. Hill, Trans.). Dordrecht: Springer.

52. Husserl, E. (2012). Zur Lehre vom Wesen und zur Methode der eidetischen Variation. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1891-1935) (Hua XLI). New York: Springer.

53. Husserl, E. (2020). Studien zur Struktur des Bewusstseins. Teilband III. Wille und Handlung. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1902-1934) (Hua XLIII/3). New York: Springer.

54. Lee, N.-I. (1993). Edmund Husserls Phdnomenologie der Instinkte. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

55. Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354-361.

56. Luft, S. (2011). Husserl's Concept of the `Transcendental Person'. In Subjectivity and Lifeworld in Transcendental Phenomenology (126-158). Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.

57. Lutz, A., Lachaux, J.-P., Martinerie, J., & Varela, F J. (2002). Guiding the Study of Brain Dynamics Using First-Person Data: Synchrony Patterns Correlate with On-going Conscious States During a Simple Visual Task. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science of the United States of America, 99 (3), 1586-1591.

58. Marosan, B. P. (2022). Husserl on Minimal Mind and the Origins of Consciousness in the Natural World. Husserl Studies, 38 (2), 107-127.

59. Maturana, H., & Varela, F J. (1980). Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

60. Mayr, E. (2004). What Makes Biology Unique? Considerations on the Autonomy of a Scientific Discipline. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

61. McGinn, C. (1989). Can We Solve the Mind-Body Problem? Mind, 98, 349-366.

62. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1967). The Structure of Behavior (A. L. Fischer, Trans.). Boston: Beacon Press.

63. Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002). Phenomenology of Perception (C. Smith, Trans.). London & New York: Routledge.

64. Moran, D. (2002). Introduction to Phenomenology. London & New York: Routledge.

65. Moran, D. (2003). Making Sense: Husserl's Phenomenology as Transcendental Idealism. In J. Malpas (Ed.), From Kant to Davidson Philosophy and the Idea of the Transcendental (48-74). London & New York: Routledge.

66. Moran, D. (2005). Edmund Husserl. Founder of Phenomenology. Cambridge, UK & Malden, USA: Polity Press.

67. Moran, D. (2008). Husserl's Transcendental Philosophy and the Critique of Naturalism. Continental Philosophy Review, 41 (4), 401-425.

68. Moran, D. (2010). Husserl and Merleau-Ponty on Embodied Experience. In T. Nennon & P. Blosser (Eds.), Advancing Phenomenology. Essays in Honor of Lester Embree (175-196). New York: Springer.

69. Moran, D. (2013a). The Phenomenology of Embodiment: Intertwining and Reflexivity. In R. T. Jensen & D. Moran (Eds.), The Phenomenology of Embodied Subjectivity (285-304). New York: Springer.

70. Moran, D. (2013b). `Let's Look at It Objectively': Why Phenomenology Cannot be Naturalized. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 72, 89-115.

71. Moran, D. (2013c). Edmund Husserl and Phenomenology. In A. Bailey (Ed.), Philosophy of Mind: The Key Thinkers (37-58). London: Bloomsbury.

72. Moran, D. (2015). Lived Body, Intercorporeality, Intersubjectivity. The Body as a Phenomenological Theme. In D. O. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou & W Hopp (Eds.), Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology. Conceptual and Empirical Approaches (57-78). London & New York: Routledge.

73. Moran, D. (2017). Lived Body, Intersubjectivity, and Intercorporeality: The Body in Phenomenology. In L. Dolezal & D. Peterbridge (Eds.), Body/Self/Other. The Phenomenology of Social Encounters (269-310). New York: Suny Press.

74. Moran, D. (2021). Husserl's Idealism Revisited. In C. D. Coe (Ed.), The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism and Phenomenology (15-40). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

75. Myin, E., & O'Regan, J. K. (2002). Perceptual Consciousness, Access to Modality, and Skill Theories: A Way to Naturalize Phenomenology? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9, 27-46.

76. Nagel, T. (1974). What Is It Like to Be a Bat? The Philosophical Review, 83 (4), 435-450.

77. Noe, A. (2021). The Enactive Approach: A Briefer Statement, with Some Remarks on “Radical Enactiv- ism”. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 20, 957-970.

78. O'Regan, J. K., & №зё, A. (2001). A Sensorimotor Account of Vision and Visual Consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939-1011.

79. Petitmengin, C., Remillieux, A., & Valenzuela-Moguillansky, C. (2018). Discovering the Structures of Lived Experience. Towards a Micro-phenomenological Analysis Method. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 18 (4), 691-730.

80. Petitot, J., Varela, F J., Pachoud, B., & Roy, J.-M. (Eds.). (1999). Naturalizing Phenomenology. Issues in Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press.

81. Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological Predicates. In W H. Capitan & D.D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, Mind, and Religion (37-48). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

82. Revonsuo, A. (2021). The Explanatory Gap: Progress and Problems. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice, 8 (1), 91-94.

83. Rupert, R. D. (2009). Cognitive Systems and the Extended Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

84. Russell, B. (1910). Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 11, 108-128.

85. Shapiro, L. (2004). The Mind Incarnate. Cambridge, Massachusetts & London: A Bradford Book, MIT Press.

86. Shapiro, L., & Spaulding, S. (2021). Embodied Cognition. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford: The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. Retrieved from: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/embodied-cognition/

87. Sokolowski, R. (1970). The Formation of Husserl's Concept of Constitution. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

88. Sokolowski, R. (2000). Introduction to Phenomenology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

89. Smith, A. D. (2003). Husserl and the Cartesian Meditations. London & New York: Routledge.

90. Smith, D. W. (1983). Husserl's Philosophy of Mind. In Contemporary Philosophy. A New Survey, Vol. 4 (249-286). Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

91. Smith, D. W. (2007). Husserl. London & New York: Routledge.

92. Smith, D. W., & McIntyre, R. (1982). Husserl and Intentionality. A Study of Mind, Meaning and Language. Dordrecht: Reidel.

93. Smith, D. W, & Thomasson, A. L. (2005). Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press & Oxford University Press.

94. Suzuki, T. (2022). The Evolutionary Origins of Consciousness. A Key to the Solution of the Hard Problem of Consciousness? Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science, 31, 53-73.

95. Tengelyi, L. (1998). Der Zwitterbegriff Lebensgeschichte. Munchen: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.

96. Tengelyi, L. (2007). Erfahrung und Ausdruck. Phanomenologie im Umbruch bei Husserl und seinen Nachfolgern. Dordrecht: Springer.

97. Tengelyi, L. (2014). Welt und Unendlichkeit. Zum Problem phanomenologischer Metaphysik. Freiburg & Munchen: Verlag Karl Alber.

98. Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life. Biology, Phenomenology and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

99. Thompson, E. (2022). Could All Life Be Sentient? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 29 (3-4), 229-265.

100. Tye, M. (2021). Qualia. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford: The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. Retrieved from https:// plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/

101. Varela, F J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

102. Varela, F J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A Methodological Remedy for the Hard Problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3 (4), 330-349.

103. Venieri, M. (2015). Embodied Mind and Phenomenal Consciousness. Argument, 5 (1), 9-23.

104. Wehrle, M. (2020). Being a Body and Having a Body. The Twofold Temporality of Embodied Intentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 19 (3), 499-521.

105. Yoshimi, J. (2010). Husserl on Psycho-physical Laws. In The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, X (25-42). London: Routledge.

106. Yoshimi, J. (2014). Narrowing the Explanatory Gap Using Bridge Metaphors. In P. Bello, M. Guarini, M. McShane & B. Scassellati (Eds.), Proceedings of the 36th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (3143-3148). Cognitive Science Society.

107. Yoshimi, J. (2022). Phenomenological Psychology as Philosophy of Mind. In H. Jacobs (Ed.), The Hus- serlian Mind (446-458). London & New York: Routledge.

108. Zahavi, D. (1994). Husserl's Phenomenology of the Body. Etudes Phenomenologiques, 19, 63-84.

109. Zahavi, D. (1996). Husserl und die transzendentale Intersubjektivitdt. Eine Antwort auf die sprachprag- matische Kritik. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

110. Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl's Phenomenology. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press.

111. Zhok, A. (2016). Possibility and Consciousness in Husserl's Thought. Husserl Studies, 32 (3), 213-235.

112. Zwaan, R. A. (2021). Two Challenges to “Embodied Cognition” Research and How to Overcome Them. Journal of Cognition, 4 (1), 1-9.

Размещено на Allbest.ru


Подобные документы

  • Biography of Pylyp Orlyk. "Pacts and the Constitution of the rights and liberties of the Army Zaporozhye", or so-called "Pylyp Orlyk's Constitution". Many interesting and progressive ideas in the constitution. Original legal platform "Mazepa’s movements".

    реферат [199,4 K], добавлен 03.03.2010

  • The Brooklyn Bridge is a popular landmark in the New York City. The History and the Structure of the Brooklyn Bridge. The Bridge and American Culture. Ethnic and foreign responses to America, nationalism, memory, commemoration, popular culture.

    реферат [13,1 K], добавлен 09.07.2013

  • Analysis of Rousseau's social contract theory and examples of its connection with the real world. Structure of society. Principles of having an efficient governmental system. Theory of separation of powers. The importance of censorship and religion.

    статья [13,1 K], добавлен 30.11.2014

  • The current Constitution of the Russian Federation was adopted by national referendum on December 12, 1993. Russia's constitution came into force on December 25, 1993, at the moment of its official publication, abolished the Soviet system of government.

    реферат [17,3 K], добавлен 22.03.2015

  • Features of the Constitution states: development and history of the formation, structure and basic elements, articles, laws. Similar and distinctive features. Comparison of the human rights section. Governance, management and system of government.

    эссе [16,2 K], добавлен 09.03.2012

  • Concept, importance of the Constitution as the fundamental law of the state, the history of development. Features of the constitutions of the leading powers of the European continent. Factors that influence the content of the Constitution of Bulgaria.

    реферат [21,4 K], добавлен 14.02.2015

  • Definition of Leadership. Trait theory. How this theory works. Origin and Analysis and basics Pre-conditions for effective use of Trait theory. Inborn leadership characteristics. Process of impact and interaction among the leader and his followers.

    реферат [436,9 K], добавлен 24.09.2014

  • History of infantilism. Formation of the civil society and development of the lawful state. About the new constitution of Serbia. Introduction of obligatory examination for all state and municipal officials of knowledge of Constitution of the Russia.

    контрольная работа [20,1 K], добавлен 10.02.2015

  • A cosmological model to explain the origins of matter, energy, space, time the Big Bang theory asserts that the universe began at a certain point in the distant past. Pre-twentieth century ideas of Universe’s origins. Confirmation of the Big Bang theory.

    реферат [37,2 K], добавлен 25.06.2010

  • Public choice is an application of neoclassical economic tools. James Buchanan the developer of the Theory of the Public choice. The most important contribution of Public Choice Theory is that it recognizes that politicians are motivated by self interest.

    презентация [273,0 K], добавлен 03.04.2012

Работы в архивах красиво оформлены согласно требованиям ВУЗов и содержат рисунки, диаграммы, формулы и т.д.
PPT, PPTX и PDF-файлы представлены только в архивах.
Рекомендуем скачать работу.